Math, asked by cuteprincess200012, 3 months ago

what is low probability thinking

Answers

Answered by kishore7869
1

Step-by-step explanation:

The way people respond to the chance that an unlikely event will occur depends on how the event is described. We propose that people attach more weight to unlikely events when they can easily generate or imagine examples in which the event has occurred or will occur than when they cannot. We tested this idea in two experiments with mock jurors using written murder scenarios. The results suggested that jurors attach more weight to the defendant's claim that an incriminating DNA match is merely coincidental when it is easy for them to imagine other individuals whose DNA would also match than when it is not easy for them to imagine such individuals. We manipulated the difficulty of imagining such examples by varying the description of the DNA-match statistic. Some of the variations that influenced the jurors were normatively irrelevant.

Answered by Ashmithajayanthilal
0

Step-by-step explanation:

The way people respond to the chance that an unlikely event will occur depends on how the event is described. We propose that people attach more weight to unlikely events when they can easily generate or imagine examples in which the event has occurred or will occur than when they cannot. We tested this idea in two experiments with mock jurors using written murder scenarios. The results suggested that jurors attach more weight to the defendant's claim that an incriminating DNA match is merely coincidental when it is easy for them to imagine other individuals whose DNA would also match than when it is not easy for them to imagine such individuals. We manipulated the difficulty of imagining such examples by varying the description of the DNA-match statistic. Some of the variations that influenced the jurors were normatively irrelevant.

Access Options

My Account

Email (required):

Password (required):

Remember me

Forgotten your password?

Need to activate?

Need Help?

Institutional Access

Shibboleth

Open Athens

Need Help?

APS Member Access

APS Member? Sign in for full access.

Not a Member? Join now for full access.

Purchase Content

24 hours online access to download content

Subscribe to this journal

Recommend to your library

Need Help?

Rent with DeepDyve

Rent Article

Research off-campus without worrying about access issues. Find out about Lean Library here

REFERENCES

Brase, G.L., Cosmides, L., Tooby, J. (1998). Individuating, counting and statistical inference: The role of frequency and whole-object representations in judgment under uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127, 3–21.

Google Scholar | Crossref

Cosmides, L., Tooby, J. (1996). Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty. Cognition, 58, 1–73.

Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI

Denes-Raj, V., Epstein, S. (1994). Conflict between intuitive and rational processing: When people behave against their better judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 819–829.

Google Scholar | Crossref | Medline | ISI

Gastwirth, J.L. (2000). Statistical science in the courtroom. New York: Springer.

Google Scholar | Crossref

Gigerenzer, G., Hoffrage, U. (1995). How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instructions: Frequency formats. Psychological Review, 102, 684–704.

Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI

Hoffrage, U., Lindsey, S., Hertwig, R., Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Communication of statistical information. Science, 290, 2261–2262.

Google Scholar | Crossref | Medline

Jones, S.K., Jones, K.T., Frisch, D. (1995). Biases of probability assessment: A comparison of frequency and single-case judgments. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 61, 109–122.

Google Scholar | Crossref

Kahneman, D., Miller, D.T. (1986). Norm theory: Comparing reality to its alternatives. Psychological Review, 92, 136–153.

Google Scholar | Crossref

Kirkpatrick, L.A., Epstein, S. (1992). Cognitive-experiential self-theory and subjective probability: Further evidence for two conceptual systems. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 534–544.

Google Scholar | Crossref | Medline | ISI

Koehler, J.J. (1997). One in millions, billions and trillions: Lessons from People v. Collins (1968) for People v. Simpson (1995). Journal of Legal Education, 47, 214–223.

Google Scholar

Koehler, J.J. (2001). When are people persuaded by DNA match statistics? Law and Human Behavior, 25, 493–513.

Google Scholar | Crossref | Medline

Koehler, J.J. (2002). [Jurors' decision making when incidence ratios are expressed with large numerators and denominators]. Unpublished raw data.

Google Scholar

Macchi, L. (1995). Pragmatic aspects of the base rate fallacy. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 48, 188–207.

Google Scholar | Crossref

Macchi, L. (2000). Partitive formulation of information in probabilistic problems: Beyond heuristics and frequency format explanations. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 82, 217–236.

Google Scholar | Crossref | Medline

Miller, D.T., Turnbull, W., McFarland, C. (1989). When a coincidence is suspicious: The role of mental simulation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 581–589.

Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI

National Research Council, Committee on DNA Forensic Science. (1996). The evaluation of forensic DNA evidence. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

Similar questions